Produktart
Zustand
Einband
Weitere Eigenschaften
Gratisversand
Land des Verkäufers
Zahlungsarten
Verkäuferbewertung
Verlag: Reclam Philipp Jun., 2021
ISBN 10: 3150140056ISBN 13: 9783150140055
Anbieter: Better World Books, Mishawaka, IN, USA
Buch
Zustand: Very Good. Used book that is in excellent condition. May show signs of wear or have minor defects.
Mehr Angebote von anderen Verkäufern bei ZVAB
Neu ab EUR 10,78
Gebraucht ab EUR 10,08
Mehr entdecken Softcover
Verlag: Harvard University Press, 2000
ISBN 10: 0674598466ISBN 13: 9780674598461
Anbieter: Better World Books, Mishawaka, IN, USA
Buch
Zustand: Very Good. Used book that is in excellent condition. May show signs of wear or have minor defects.
ISBN 10: 3518577174ISBN 13: 9783518577172
Anbieter: medimops, Berlin, Deutschland
Buch
Befriedigend/Good: Durchschnittlich erhaltenes Buch bzw. Schutzumschlag mit Gebrauchsspuren, aber vollständigen Seiten. / Describes the average WORN book or dust jacket that has all the pages present.
Mehr Angebote von anderen Verkäufern bei ZVAB
Gebraucht ab EUR 10,07
Verlag: John Wiley & Sons, 1984
ISBN 10: 0631135219ISBN 13: 9780631135210
Anbieter: WorldofBooks, Goring-By-Sea, WS, Vereinigtes Königreich
Buch
Paperback. Zustand: Very Good. The book has been read, but is in excellent condition. Pages are intact and not marred by notes or highlighting. The spine remains undamaged.
Mehr Angebote von anderen Verkäufern bei ZVAB
Neu ab EUR 30,82
Gebraucht ab EUR 24,44
Mehr entdecken Softcover
Verlag: Suhrkamp Verlag AG, 2005
ISBN 10: 3518286560ISBN 13: 9783518286562
Anbieter: Blackwell's, Oxford, OX, Vereinigtes Königreich
Buch
paperback. Zustand: New. Language: ger.
Mehr Angebote von anderen Verkäufern bei ZVAB
Neu ab EUR 16,53
Gebraucht ab EUR 13,80
Mehr entdecken Softcover
Verlag: Stuttgart Reclam, 2014
ISBN 10: 3150109663ISBN 13: 9783150109663
Anbieter: Neusser Buch & Kunst Antiquariat, Neuss, NRW, Deutschland
Buch
0. 20 cm. 236 S. engl. brosch. Gering bestossen, sehr schöner Zustand. Sprache: Deutschutsch 0,400 gr.
Mehr Angebote von anderen Verkäufern bei ZVAB
Gebraucht ab EUR 14,00
Verlag: MINUIT, 1982
ISBN 10: 2707305979ISBN 13: 9782707305978
Anbieter: Gallix, Gif sur Yvette, Frankreich
Buch
Zustand: Neuf.
Verlag: Editions de Minuit, 1982
ISBN 10: 2707305928ISBN 13: 9782707305923
Buch
Couverture souple. Zustand: bon. RO40223123: 1982. In-8. Broché. Bon état, Couv. convenable, Dos satisfaisant, Intérieur frais. 173 pages. . . . Classification Dewey : 810-Littérature américaine.
Verlag: Minuit éditions (2/1982), 1982
Anbieter: BOOKIT!, Genève, Schweiz
Zustand: Used: Like New. LIVRE A L?ETAT DE NEUF. EXPEDIE SOUS 3 JOURS OUVRES. NUMERO DE SUIVI COMMUNIQUE AVANT ENVOI, EMBALLAGE RENFORCE. EAN:9782707305978.
ISBN 10: 3518064223ISBN 13: 9783518064221
Anbieter: medimops, Berlin, Deutschland
Buch
Befriedigend/Good: Durchschnittlich erhaltenes Buch bzw. Schutzumschlag mit Gebrauchsspuren, aber vollständigen Seiten. / Describes the average WORN book or dust jacket that has all the pages present.
Verlag: Frankfurt am Main : Suhrkamp, 1987
ISBN 10: 3518578324ISBN 13: 9783518578322
Anbieter: Chiemgauer Internet Antiquariat GbR, Altenmarkt, BAY, Deutschland
Buch Erstausgabe
Gewebe. Zustand: Gut. 1. Auflage. ERSTAUSGABE. 185 S. ; 21 cm Auf dem Innendeckel, durch den Klappentext verdeckt, Besitzerschildchen eines nicht unbedeutenden deutschen Philosophen, mit Popper und Jaspers befreundet. Aus dessen Bibliothek mit einigen Bleistiftanstreichungen und Randbemerkungen. Sonst aber FRISCHES, SEHR schönes Exemplar der ERSTAUSGABE. Sprache: Deutsch Gewicht in Gramm: 328.
Verlag: Wiley 1981-07-23, Oxford, 1981
ISBN 10: 0631128018ISBN 13: 9780631128014
Anbieter: Blackwell's, Oxford, OX, Vereinigtes Königreich
Buch
paperback. Zustand: New. Language: ENG.
Mehr Angebote von anderen Verkäufern bei ZVAB
Neu ab EUR 26,07
Verlag: SEUIL, 1996
ISBN 10: 2020172798ISBN 13: 9782020172790
Anbieter: Gallix, Gif sur Yvette, Frankreich
Buch
Zustand: Neuf.
Anbieter: Jürgen Patzer, Konstanz, Deutschland
Verlag: Suhrkamp Verlag AG Apr 2006, 2006
ISBN 10: 3518293834ISBN 13: 9783518293836
Anbieter: AHA-BUCH GmbH, Einbeck, Deutschland
Buch
Taschenbuch. Zustand: Neu. Neuware - »Was heißt: einer Regel folgen «Saul Kripke sieht in dieser Frage das zentrale Problem von Wittgensteins Spätphilosophie. Wittgenstein, so Kripke, präsentiere ein skeptisches Paradox, das zu zeigen scheine, daß der Begriff »einer Regel folgen« nicht verständlich sei. Nach einer Diskussion von wahrscheinlichen Antworten Wittgensteins auf mögliche Lösungen dieses Problems stellt Kripke Wittgensteins eigene »skeptische« Lösung dar - so wie er, Kripke, sie versteht. Sie hat weitreichende Konsequenzen für Wittgensteins Philosophie der Sprache und bildet die Grundlage für seine späteren Untersuchungen zur Philosophie der Mathematik.In einem ausführlichen Postskriptum geht Kripke vom Problem der Privatsprache weiter zu einer überraschenden Diskussion von Wittgensteins Auffassungen über das Problem des Fremdpsychischen. Kripkes Wittgenstein-Interpretation ist ein Glanzstück der Sprachphilosophie und mittlerweile selbst ein Klassiker.
Mehr Angebote von anderen Verkäufern bei ZVAB
Neu ab EUR 17,00
Gebraucht ab EUR 15,00
Mehr entdecken Softcover
Verlag: FfM: Suhrkamp Vlg. 1981., 1981
Anbieter: Antiquariat Bergische Bücherstube Mewes, Overath, Deutschland
191 S. Lit.verz. Reg. Br.
Verlag: Suhrkamp, Frankfurt, 1981
Anbieter: Antiquariat Mackensen & Niemann, Berlin, Deutschland
Erstausgabe
Deutsche Erstausgabe, Theorie, übersetzt von Ursula Wolf, 191 S., sehr gutes Exemplar, Original-Leinen mit Originalumschlag,
Verlag: Blackwell Scientific Publishers Ltd (7/1981), 1981
Anbieter: BOOKIT!, Genève, Schweiz
Zustand: Used: Like New. LIVRE A L?ETAT DE NEUF. EXPEDIE SOUS 3 JOURS OUVRES. NUMERO DE SUIVI COMMUNIQUE AVANT ENVOI, EMBALLAGE RENFORCE. EAN:9780631128014.
Verlag: Frankfurt / M., Suhrkamp,, 1987
Anbieter: Antiquariat Walter Markov, Bonn, Deutschland
Buch
185 S., *-*-*-*- SHIPPING COSTS to other EU-COUNTRIES occasionally may be less than indicated. To OTHER COUNTRIES IN THE WORLD they may be different (often less or rarely more, according to the weight and wether you wish insurance). -*-*-*-* Sprache: Deutsch Gewicht in Gramm: 360 OLn., OSU, insgesamt gering nachgedunkelt, ansonsten guter Zustand.
Verlag: Oxford University Press [2013], Oxford, 2013
Anbieter: Evening Star Books, ABAA/ILAB, Madison, WI, USA
Hardcover. Zustand: Very Good+. Zustand des Schutzumschlags: Near Fine. Fourth Printing. 8vo. [8], ix-xiii, [3], 3-170 pp. Black paper boards with silver lettering on the spine. A kind of sequel to Naming and Necessity, Kripke's classic work in the philosophy of language and metaphysics. Difficult to find in hardcover format. Minor wear to the corners and pencil annotations in the margins; jacket with trifling edge wear.
Verlag: OUP USA 2013-06-06, New York, 2013
ISBN 10: 019992838XISBN 13: 9780199928385
Anbieter: Blackwell's, Oxford, OX, Vereinigtes Königreich
Buch
hardback. Zustand: New. Language: ENG.
Verlag: New York. Oxford University Press., 2011
ISBN 10: 0199730156ISBN 13: 9780199730155
Anbieter: Antiquariat Bernhardt, Kassel, Deutschland
Buch
Karton. Außen leichte Lagerspuren. 388 Seiten, Englisch 712g.
Verlag: Harvard University Press, 1982
ISBN 10: 0674954009ISBN 13: 9780674954007
Anbieter: Books From California, Simi Valley, CA, USA
Buch
Hardcover. Zustand: Good. Excessive markings.
Verlag: Harvard University Press, 1980
ISBN 10: 0674598458ISBN 13: 9780674598454
Anbieter: ThriftBooksVintage, Tukwila, WA, USA
Buch
Hardcover. Zustand: Very Good. No Jacket. Second printing. Minor shelf and handling wear, overall a clean solid copy with minimal signs of use. Boards betray fading and nicks and other signs of wear and imperfection commensurate with age. Binding is tight and structurally sound. Pages absent any extraneous marks. New mylar added to ensure future enjoyment. Secure packaging for safe delivery.
Oxford, Blackwell, (1982). 8vo. Orig. full cloth w. gilt lettering to spine, minor bumping to capitals, otherwise a near mint copy in the orig. d-j., which is also near mint. X, 150 pp. First edition of the immensely influential work on Wittgenstein by the exceedingly influential and important logician and philosopher of language, Saul Aaron Kripke. Kripke was professor of philosophy in America, and his works are quite rare, since many of them remain unpublished and are only known in privately circulated manuscripts. In 2001 he received the Schock Prize in Logic and Philosophy. Kripke is renowned for his studies of Wittgenstein, which are printed in this work for the first time. The subject of Kripke's book is usually referred to as "Kripkenstein", since the results (as well as the method) have very little to do with what is commonly accepted as the philosophy of Wittgenstein. Kripke's main claim in this (in)famous book is that all previous commentaries on Wittgenstein's Philosophische Untersuchungen (Philosophical Investigations) have failed to understand W.'s argument against "private language". According to Kripke Wittgenstein's "private language argument" is principally to be explicated in terms of the problem of "following a rule". The "meaning scepticism" presented in this work has caused a wide range of secondary litterature and very harsh critique. The book has been called a scandal of philosophy, and the number of well-esteemed philosophers who have lined up to criticise the book is very large indeed. Among these can be found Noam Chomsky, John Searle, Peter Winch, Gordon Baker etc etc. However flawed the reading of Wittgenstein is considered to be, though, the work has received overwhealming attention, and is considered highly important and interesting.
Verlag: Association for Symbolic Logic
Erstausgabe
Zustand: Very Good. Groningen: Published for the Association for Symbolic Logic, Inc. by N. V. Erven P. Noordhoff, 1959. 1 vols bound in 4. 1st Edition. 1-96; 97-192; 192-286; 287-374+[2]+vi. Small 4to. Original printed tan wrappers. Wrappers lightly soiled & chipped, with a watermark to the lower wrapper corner at the foot of volume 1, some chipping to spine ends, dates in faded ink to the spines of vol 1 and 2, lightly bumped corners; VG copies. Quite uncommon. All four issues of volume 24 included. Weight: 1 pound 7.0 ounces = 655 grams. Size: 10.0 x 7.0 x 1.1 inches = 25 x 17.5 x 2.8cm. Lars Svenonius's copy, unsigned. Inquire if you need further information. Gach.
(No place), The Association for Symbolic Logic, 1959. Lev8vo. Bound in red half cloth with gilt lettering to spine. In "Journal of Symbolic Logic", Volume 24. Barcode label pasted on to back board. Small library stamp to lower part of 6 pages. A very fine copy. Pp. (1) - 14. [Entire volume: VI, 374 pp.). The seminal first printing of Kripke's debut article, which provided the basis for his logic and for the model theory for modal logic in general. The work constitutes the very beginning of Kripke Semantics (often called possible world semantics). Kripke's works in general are rare in fist editions. Many of them remain unpublished and are only known in privately circulated manuscripts.The American philosopher Saul A. Kripke (born 1940) is an exceedingly important logician and philosopher of language and one of the most powerful and influential thinkers of analytic and Anglo-American philosophy. He is considered the greatest living philosopher and perhaps the greatest since Wittgenstein. In 2001 he was awarded the Schock Prize in Logic and Philosophy, which is considered the philosopical equivalent of the Nobel Prize.Kripke, who grew up in Omaha in a religious Jewish family, was somewhat of a prodigy child. During grammar school he got intimately acquainted with and mastered to perfection algebra, geometry and calculus, and very early on he took up philosophy, which later became his career. Still a teenager, in high school, he wrote a work that was to change the face of philosophical logic forever, namely the groundbreaking paper "A Completeness Theorem for Modal Logic", which was printed a few years later, in 1959, in the Journal of Symbolic Logic, while he was in his first year at Harvard University. This seminal debut work proposed what later came to be known as Kripke models for modal logic. The story goes that the paper earned a letter from the department of mathematics urging Kripke to apply for a job there, to which he is said to have written an answer explaining "My mother said that I should finish high school and go to college first."In 1962 he graduated from Harvard University, where he remained until 1968, first as a member of the Harvard Society of Fellows and then as a lecturer. During these years he developed the logical theories founded in the "Completeness Theorem" further and made seminal contributions to the field of logic and semantics. Kripke Semantics is a formal semantics for non-classical logic systems that Kripke began developing in his teenage years, first published something on in 1959 (the present work) and further developed in the 60'ies and. The development of Kripke Semantics was no less than a breakthrough in the making of non-classical logics, of which no model theory existed before Kripke's. With this work, Kripke laid the foundation for proving completeness theorems for modal logic, and for identifying the weakest normal modal logic, which is now named K after him.
(No place), The Association for Symbolic Logic, 1959. 8vo. Orig. printed wrappers. An excellent copy in near mint condition, in- as well as externally. Pp. (1) - 14. (The entire volume: 96 pp.). The seminal first printing of Kripke's debut article, which provided the basis for his logic and for the model theory for modal logic in general. The work constitutes the very beginning of Kripke Semantics (often called possible world semantics). Kripke's works in general are rare in fist editions. Many of them remain unpublished and are only known in privately circulated manuscripts.The American philosopher Saul A. Kripke (born 1940) is an exceedingly important logician and philosopher of language and one of the most powerful and influential thinkers of analytic and Anglo-American philosophy. He is considered the greatest living philosopher and perhaps the greatest since Wittgenstein. In 2001 he was awarded the Schock Prize in Logic and Philosophy, which is considered the philosopical equivalent of the Nobel Prize.Kripke, who grew up in Omaha in a religious Jewish family, was somewhat of a prodigy child. During grammar school he got intimately acquainted with and mastered to perfection algebra, geometry and calculus, and very early on he took up philosophy, which later became his career. Still a teenager, in high school, he wrote a work that was to change the face of philosophical logic forever, namely the groundbreaking paper "A Completeness Theorem for Modal Logic", which was printed a few years later, in 1959, in the Journal of Symbolic Logic, while he was in his first year at Harvard University. This seminal debut work proposed what later came to be known as Kripke models for modal logic. The story goes that the paper earned a letter from the department of mathematics urging Kripke to apply for a job there, to which he is said to have written an answer explaining "My mother said that I should finish high school and go to college first."In 1962 he graduated from Harvard University, where he remained until 1968, first as a member of the Harvard Society of Fellows and then as a lecturer. During these years he developed the logical theories founded in the "Completeness Theorem" further and made seminal contributions to the field of logic and semantics. Kripke Semantics is a formal semantics for non-classical logic systems that Kripke began developing in his teenage years, first published something on in 1959 (the present work) and further developed in the 60'ies and. The development of Kripke Semantics was no less than a breakthrough in the making of non-classical logics, of which no model theory existed before Kripke's. With this work, Kripke laid the foundation for proving completeness theorems for modal logic, and for identifying the weakest normal modal logic, which is now named K after him.
Verlag: [No place:] The Association for Symbolic Logic, Inc., March 1959, 1959
Anbieter: Peter Harrington. ABA/ ILAB., London, Vereinigtes Königreich
Erstausgabe
First edition, first printing, of the author's first major work, published when he was only 18 years old, which provided the foundations for Kripke's innovations in modal logic and semantics. Saul Kripke (1940-2022) was "one of the most penetrating minds of our time. His achievements span the disciplines of philosophy, logic and mathematics. From his post at Princeton University, where he was James McCosh Professor of Philosophy, and his previous post at Rockefeller University, Kripke established a towering reputation as one of the two or three most eminent philosophers in the English-speaking world.Kripke's contributions to philosophy have extended the boundaries of the most unfamiliar and technical regions of modern analytic philosophy - where philosophical reasoning intermingles with abstract mathematic theory. He worked in the field of modal logic, a branch of formal logic that has introduced ways to distinguish kinds of true statements. Before Kripke, modal logicians - including the inventor of modal logic, C. I. Lewis - did not have the mathematical tools to analyze many of the most important kinds of English sentences. One of Kripke's major achievements was the invention of 'possible world semantics,' a form of modal logic that has shown to the satisfaction of most philosophers that the common-sense understanding of the concepts 'possibility' and 'necessity' in true statements can be mathematically proved" (Branch, p. 180). Taylor Branch, "New Frontiers in American Philosophy", The New York Times, 14 August 1977. Octavo, pp. 1-14 in the journal. Original buff wrappers printed in black. A couple of tears to spine, chip at foot neatly reglued, contents clean: a near-fine copy.
Anbieter: Patrik Andersson, Antikvariat., Lund, Schweden
Erstausgabe
Oxford; Basil Blackwell, 1982. First edition. 22,5x14,5 cm. x, 150 pp. Publisher's boards with printed dustjacket. Spine ends are slightly bumped, and there is an insignificant scrape mark on front board. A fine copy. Kripke's famous reading of Wittgenstein's "Philosophical Investigations", in which he coins the term "Kripkenstein", referring to a fictional character who agrees with the views expressed by Kripke's reading of Wittgenstein.